The legacy of Greece and Rome to the modern world is far from consisting only of literature. The Renaissance began in Italy, where the physical remains of antiquity were everywhere visible. Enormous ruins, temples and aqueducts and theaters, dominated Rome and many other cities. In an outpost of Empire like Britain, where things were on a more provincial scale, that is not so, and the sheer size of the Pantheon and the Coliseum still comes as a surprise to northerners.

Another aspect of that legacy was the precious treasures surviving from the wreck of the high culture. The Vatican, like the great treasures of Vienna and Paris, still possesses marvels of ancient luxury, valued as much for their materials as for their artistic quality: cameos, and carved crystals, and mosaics, and statues in rare and precious stones. These works fall rather outside what is classed as serious or major art by modern taste, and the cultivated tourist no longer regards as the first priority in London or Vienna such objects as the Augustan Gem in Vienna (a large cameo depicting the apotheosis of Augustus) and the Portland Vase in the British museum (a virtuoso creation in layered and carved glass once believed to be of precious stone.)

The Renaissance knew very little of the Greek gold work, both jewelry and objets de luxe, which in the last 150 years has come to light in great quantities. People of that period would have been fascinated by the exhibition “The Gold of Greece,” recently on show in London and New York; but nowadays such a spectacle has a faintly middle-brow air. Serious scholars are embarrassed by the decorative arts, and one does not expect contemporary artists to be inspired by its splendors at any level more ambitious than that of the museum gift shop and the manufacture of replicas in less expensive metal. Ancient jewelry has come down in the world, at least academically, in recent centuries.

By contrast, Greek vases have gone up. For the popes of the sixteenth century, as for the milords of the eighteenth, the vases which were of interest were not the pottery ones which now populate our museums and are the subject of so many books on Greek vase painting, but the few huge carved ones in stone, like the Borghese Vase and the Medici Vase, both five feet high, ascribed (optimistically) to no less an artist than Phidias, and reckoned among the supreme works of art. They were copied in marble at Versailles, in bronze at Osterley Park, in alabaster at Houghton Hall, and in silver gilt—and in a set of eight—by the goldsmith Paul Storr for the Prince Regent. The originals are now respectively in the Louvre and the Uffizi.

It was in the second half of the eighteenth century that serious attention began to be given to the pottery vessels which were coming to light in great numbers from tombs in Italy and Sicily. So many of them came from Tuscany that they were at first not believed to be Greek. They were called “Etruscan vases,” and Josiah Wedgwood named his pottery works “Etruria” on that account (1769). Their inexpensive material and simple but elegant shapes made a great appeal to a period in which many people were attuned to Rousseau and increasingly repelled by the rococo. There had always been a tradition which deplored excessive luxury and ornamentation at the table and in the house; that tradition now was triumphant. Determined efforts were made to induce the public to like and admire these simpler products of ancient Greece: not least by collectors and dealers.

That is indeed a recurrent note in the story. Sir William Hamilton, British envoy to the court of Naples, was a great collector; he had picked up, and married, the celebrated beauty Emma Hart, who as Emma Hamilton was to inspire painters and to scandalize and delight Europe as the mistress of Nelson. He bought the largest and most desirable of ancient marble vases, the Warwick Vase (discovered in 1771; now in Glasgow). He also amassed an extensive collection of Greek pots, which the British Museum finally bought for £8,000; not without an energetic propaganda campaign and the publication of a sumptuous catalog in four grandiose volumes, filled with encomiums of the beauty and value of the objects illustrated.

Greek vases became the rage (they are “vases” to their admirers, “pots” to those who think them overvalued). Goethe was not unmoved. In his famous Italienische Reise he says,

We were taken back into earlier epochs by inspecting a precious vase of considerable size and perfect preservation. People pay a lot of money now for Etruscan vases, and certainly one finds beautiful and exquisite pieces among them. Every traveller wants one. People do not value their money so highly as they do at home; I was afraid that I might be tempted myself…

No better publicity could be imagined. Munich and Berlin followed the trend. Soon every national museum and many universities had fine collections. Prices went up and up, and they are still high: more than £2 million has been paid for a single piece of Athenian painted pottery.

Advertisement

Vases or pots? We are dealing with the tableware of antiquity, the cups from which people drank, the pitchers and bowls from which they served. This is not, that is to say, a “pure” art, like the making of statues or easel pictures, with no end beyond the aesthetic one: these things were made for daily use. What was their standing in antiquity? After the publication of the Hamilton catalog it was often asserted or assumed that the status of Greek potters was high, that big prices were paid for fine pots, and that their productions were cherished and used by the elite. They were, in fact, in the full sense works of art.

The study of these vases later became a respected branch of scholarship. That is due above all to the genius of Sir John Beazley (1885-1970), a critic gifted with a marvelous eye and memory, who also wrote very well. He spent a long life on distinguishing and attributing the painted vases to individual artists; and his results turned a rather hit-and-miss affair into an orderly and scholarly one. A range of “schools,” “studios,” and “masters” fell into place, on the model of the artists of the Italian Renaissance; Beazley used the method of Giovanni Morelli, who pointed out that painters have their own characteristic formulae for ears, nostrils, and the like, and that their study enabled the patient and perceptive inquirer to identify the work of each individual artist. Beazley’s results, and his method, have been generally accepted as authoritative.

For some years now Michael Vickers, of the Ashmolean Museum in Oxford, and David Gill, of the University College of Swansea, have been attacking this consensus. Artful Crafts is an exposition (and repetition) of their case, and it is entertaining as well as scholarly. They argue that in the ancient word the pots were in reality of low price and little esteemed; that their shapes and their decoration alike derive from the objects which really were highly valued, namely, vessels in gold and silver, for which pottery was no more than a cheap substitute; that consequently there were no real, original artists among the potters; and—they say aggressively—

The practice of rich collection and dealers employing a learned hack to publish or puff their “vases” has inevitably meant that the status of the material, and of the craftsmen who produced it, has been exaggerated and that market imperatives have resulted in the suspension of critical judgment on the part of those otherwise best equipped to discuss the question of value.

Fighting words; and the authors go on to say, with some complacency, “We are reliably informed (by a former ancient-art consultant) that one consequence of our thesis is that some North American collectors are now questioning the wisdom of acquiring painted pottery, since the field is now so controversial (and nothing puts off collectors as much as controversy: they want their investments to be secure and not subject to the vagaries of scholarship.)

We have here assertions of more than one sort. On the first point, that painted pottery was not “especially valuable” in Greece, I think the case is proved. It should be said, however, despite the polemical energy here put into refuting the opposite view, that there is disconcertingly little evidence, from the sources cited here, that anyone much has held it; at least recently. The ancient writers hardly ever mention painted pottery, and such scraps of evidence as there are for ancient prices suggest that it was very inexpensive; surprisingly so, in fact. Both Persian kings and Roman emperors are described as serving pottery cups at table to individuals whom they wanted to punish or humiliate, everybody else drinking as usual from precious metal. Artful Crafts contains an amusing account of early modern scholars glossing over these facts or blandly stating the opposite. The authors are also right to insist that plate, precious metal, was what people wanted in antiquity, at the periods when they could afford it; as many of then could in Athens in the fifth century BCE, when the spoils of King Xerxes’ failed invasion, the booming local production of silver, and the profits of their empire, together meant that the upper class possessed more bullion than at any time before the conquests of Alexander the Great flooded Greece with the treasure of the East.

We possess very little of that plate. As in many other periods, it was constantly being melted down; there was as little respect for old styles and craftsmanship as there was in the seventeenth century. And it was not the custom at that time, any more than it is now, to bury treasures with the dead. It is consequently only from the fringes of the Greek world that we recover a few of the spectacular golden objects which existed; for in southern Russia and in Macedon that custom still prevailed. It is important to remember that the ancients loved richness, as well as simplicity. Their taste, in fact, resembled that of the Renaissance, in some important respects, more closely than it resembles ours.

Advertisement

Adolf Loos, propagandist for the Modern Movement, said in 1908, “Greek vases are as beautiful as a machine, as beautiful as a bicycle.” Terence Conran said in 1984, “To be simple in decoration is always to be in good taste.” Those opinions, essentially moral but masquerading as aesthetics, express the dominant taste of the twentieth century, and it is one to which the simple shapes and plain earthenware of Greek pottery make a strong appeal. We are not at ease with sumptuous materials; an Oxford colleague (not a man of notably abstemious life) expressed embarrassed surprise at finding me gazing into a jeweler’s window. But the ancients did not think the supreme aesthetic merit was the avoidance of risk. Visitors to Thessaloniki who see the recently discovered gold and silver treasures buried with Philip, the father of Alexander, will find in them a combination of purity and opulence.

The next point, that the design of the pots is entirely derivative from vessels in metal, is not so easy to accept, in that strong form. Vickers and Gill point to undeniable instances where pottery objects imitate metal ones, even in such details as reproducing the rivets which hold a metal piece together. Clearly the shapes, too, of metal and ceramic often go together. The phenomenon is familiar in other traditions, notably China and the Islamic world. It is perhaps not so certain that the influence between pottery and metal must always have been in the same direction; and a question remains in the mind. The art of pottery is a very ancient one in Greece, and the early pots do not look clearly derivative from another medium. Were things so simple in the classical period?

Another theory has been much discussed since Vickers first put it forward. The colors of classical pottery are to be derived from those of metalwork, as the pots themselves resemble the precious vessels for which they are a cheap substitute. Thus the famous lustrous black is a representation of tarnished silver, while red stands for gold. Of the less important colors, white stands for ivory, and purple stands for copper. Black and red are the central points here. If there are granted, then the main color scheme of Athenian pottery is conceded to have been derived from the cheap imitation of another art. It is not easy to concede this, and one has sympathy with Sir John Boardman, one of Beazley’s successors and an upholder of that tradition, who gave to an article written in protest the title “Silver is White.”1 Vickers and Gill, by contrast, refer to “the shiny black sheen of pure silver which we believe potters to have attempted to evoke with their black slips.”

It is true that indications can be found that there was at some times in antiquity, as there has sometimes been since, tolerance of tarnishing in silver. Although Greek pottery consistently uses “silver” of such ambiguously white things as the feet of a sea-nymph, the moon, and the whirlpools of rivers, while the adjective which the fifth-century poet Euripides chooses for silver is “bright,” it is not impossible that silver sometimes appeared on sideboards deeply discolored. What is harder to believe is that the color chosen to represent this would have been the glossy pitch black so familiar in Athenian pots. Nobody has ever really seen silver looking like that; and if the intention was indeed to simulate the metal, this is more than a debating point. The red is a better likeness of gold, but as Martin Robertson points out in his recent Art of Vase-Painting in Classical Athens,2 there are some vases known on which actual gold details were added on the red, a fact which hardly supports that analysis. In fact deception can surely not have been the point. An Attic pot decorated in red and black may be said to have a resemblance to one in silver and gold, but it is a resemblance transformed into something else: into a different art form. A distinctive aesthetic of ceramics still remains. Nor is it certain that pots in silver and gold existed in Greece at a date early enough (circa 630 BCE) to explain the first Attic vases.

On the other hand, the white, painted pots, which were especially associated with funerals, and which have a characteristic tubular shape, do indeed strongly resemble sections of elephant tusks, and an origin from ivory is attractive. The National Museum in Athens contains a splendid collection of these lekythoi, decorated with drawings of moving simplicity.3 We have a few precious examples of Greek drawings on ivory; and ivory was often in evidence at funerals.

Vickers and Gill also argue that the designs of the painted decoration on pottery were copied from those on plate, and with such slavishness that the occasional signatures of makers on vases simply write out names of the smiths visible on the metal originals. It is fair to point, in partial reply, to the known pots on which the painter has left visible pentimenti, lines remaining from an earlier version of the final design. That suggests, at least in those cases, something other than mechanical copying. It is perfectly true that many pots resemble one another very closely; but there ay be more explanations than one for that.

Finally the question must be faced: If these pots really were cheap and of little account in antiquity, does it follow that they must forfeit their high status (and monetary value) among us? Vickers and Gill seem convinced of it. “All such pot decoration… was done in a manner which consciously echoed the appearance of more precious objects whether of silver, gold, ivory, or bronze”; and “if there is a possibility that most Greek pottery vases are ‘mock silver,’ then obvious questions arise about the respect in which they (and their executants) have been held in modern times.”

That is to say: the crucial questions are of intention (“consciously echoed”) and of truth to the valuation placed on the work in the original society: “To be a potter was not a praiseworthy calling,” and the stuff was inexpensive. When the authors admit that “many of the surviving pots are well made and skillfully decorated,” even that rather grudging admission is made in wounding terms. The last words of the book are: “If Greek standards of craftsmanship were high in the medium of ceramic, this will have been because standards were set by workers in other, nobler, materials.” There is a constant emphasis here on cash value: pottery cannot be of any account, they come close to saying, because it did not cost enough. As they detect echoes of the Arts and Crafts movement in ceramophile writers of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, so we perhaps catch here a resonance of the all too streetwise 1990s.

I cannot quite resist a sense that the authors, who are very crisp in their response when other people pass off moral views as aesthetic criticism, are guilty of something rather similar themselves. Whether an artifact is or is not admirable, whether it is a work of art, surely depends crucially on its own qualities, on what we see as we actually look at it; not on what we infer about the intentions or the status of its creator, or about the price set on it long ago. There was a time in Europe when drawings were not taken seriously as finished works, either by artists or by patrons. We value medieval drawings highly: Are we obviously wrong?

Vickers and Gill make their case that pottery did not enjoy high status in classical Greece. They are also quite right to insist on the importance of precious metal: “The main purpose of this book has been to reinsert gold and silver plate into the general picture of antiquity.” Some of the pieces they discuss are fascinating and little known, notably the silver vessels with gold decoration now in Leningrad and Plovdiv (Bulgaria): magnificent objects, known for half a century, and, as they sardonically observe, never illustrated in histories of Greek art. They are too opulent for the puritanical taste of modern scholars.

As for Attic pottery, it may be granted that most of it is run-of-the-mill domestic stuff of no great distinction; a trip around the collection in any major museum will confirm, only too wearyingly, a fact which is essentially unsurprising, though not often explicitly faced. It is less than just, however, not to grant that Attic ware of the fifth century rarely fails to be shapely and comely. And I agree with Goethe that the best of it can be “beautiful and exquisite”—as well as showing us something of Greek mythology and domestic and sexual life we cannot learn elsewhere. There are dozens of pieces for which, if I were rich, I should be prepared to give a lot—even after reading this lively, intelligent, highly polemical book.

This Issue

June 8, 1995